Legal Realism and the Social Contract:
Fuller's Public Jurisprudence of Form, Private Jurisprudence of Substance
James Boyle(1) © 1992
{A later version of this article appeared in 78 Cornell Law
Review 371 (1993)}
One seldom encounters a law review article today of the type so common
ten years ago, in which the writer starts with an inquiry into the "nature"
of some legal concept and ends by deducing all sorts of important consequences
from the supposed inner nature of the concept--without more than a passing
reference to the practical effects of his conclusions, and then with an
air of condescension, as if to compliment the facts for showing good judgment
in conforming to his theories. Lon Fuller, American Legal Realism
(1934)(2)
A total failure in any one of these eight directions does not simply
result in a bad system of law; it results in something that is not properly
called a legal system at all, except perhaps in the Pickwickian sense in
which a void contract can still be said to be one kind of contract.
Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law (1964).(3)
Introduction: This article is a contribution to the theoretical
and historical literature about Lon Fuller, a figure who is of interest
both for his own sake and because of his "iconic" role in the
history of legal thought over the last fifty years.(4)
At the same time, the article aspires to make a broader argument about
the relevance of legal realism to the social contract tradition in political
theory. My argument begins with the discovery of an apparent conflict between
the "public"(5) and the "private"
jurisprudence of contract in Fuller's work. Describing contracts in private
law, Fuller gave an account that owed a great deal to legal realism, particularly
in the way that it attacked formalistic criteria for enforceability. Where
the classicists stressed form and consideration as theoretical a prioris,
Fuller subjected those ideas to functional scrutiny, decried the undervaluation
of the reliance principle and found reasons for enforceability in relative
and contingent community norms. Fuller accepts that Section 90 of the second
Restatement may require the judge to step in post hoc and to create
enforceable bargains where it is necessary "to prevent injustice,"(6)
he portrays the formal requirements of contract as being in dialectical,
productive tension with their functional goals, and he denies that the
rules of contract law are somehow immanent within the very definition of
a contract.
In his more general jurisprudential writing however, when Fuller describes the "morality that makes law possible" he has in mind a set of formal criteria that define, or perhaps it would be better to say are deduced from, the very meaning of law. In this vision, for example, the abuse of retroactive legislation does not merely result in bad law, but in rules that are not law at all. From his comments about reciprocity between state and citizen, it would seem that Fuller thought he could deduce his eight formal and necessary principles of legality from the social contract. Yet the vision he gives of the social contract seems to conflict with his vision of a private contract. In the latter case Fuller writes more like a realist, in the former, more like a formalist. Fuller the early contracts theorist apparently undermines the claims made by the Fuller the later jurisprude. This article explores the roots of that conflict. My aim is to clarify our picture of Fuller, but also to come to some more general understanding of the relationship of political theory and doctrinal analysis. My argument is that legal and social theorists have been slow to see the parallels between the problems of contractualism and the problems of contract law, between the contract for chickens and the social contract, between the problems of Willistonian will theory and the problems of original intent. In the conclusion I offer some tentative suggestions about the relationship of legal realism to the theory and rhetoric of the social contract.
I
A Conflict?
Lon Fuller was one of the greatest of American legal thinkers, and in
not one but two fields.(7) Students today
still read a contracts casebook that bears Fuller's name and includes a
(sadly diminishing amount of) his scholarship on contracts.(8)
Chief among that body of work is his famous article, The Reliance Interest
in Contract Damages,(9) although his
review of Williston on Contracts(10) and
his Columbia Law Review essay Consideration and Form(11)
are perhaps even more worthy of notice. In those works, Fuller provided
a vital part of the theoretical apparatus necessary to go beyond the classical
Willistonian idea of contract. He argued that contract should not be considered
as an "in or out" category, that in fact there was an "ascending
scale of enforceability."(12) He criticized
the psychological language of assent and implied conditions in which the
First Restatement framed its substantive positions on enforceable and unenforceable
bargains.(13) He was openly skeptical of
the possibility of classifying contracts through some general list of formal
desiderata.(14) Above all, he was
an able critic of the idea that contracts should only be seen as
arising out of individual autonomy expressed through form and exchange.(15)
To supplement this idea of contract, he focused instead on justified reliance
and thus explicitly introduced reference to notions of community norms
and shared understanding.(16) By making
enforceability dependent on the particular social understandings in which
behaviour was embedded, Fuller posed the single most effective challenge
of his time to the notion that there was some set of trans-social, formal
criteria that could allow us to distinguish contract from non-contract.
Fuller's second -- and to jurisprudential eyes, greater -- contribution
lay in the realm of general legal theory. Students still read the Case
of the Speluncean Explorers,(17) or
Fuller's debates with H.L.A. Hart over "Positivism and Fidelity to
Law."(18) In this incarnation, Fuller
is presented as the proponent of purposive interpretation. The argument
imputed to him here is that even the easiest case is answered by a subconscious
exploration of the purposes of a rule, and that more complex cases should,
and generally are, resolved by a more conscious exploration of purpose
and intent. With simple examples and unusually accessible linguistic arguments,
Fuller criticized the notion that there are core meanings to words and
that those core meanings generally allow judges to decide cases without
recourse to consideration of purpose or policy. This part of his work was
a vital inspiration to the early critical legal studies work on interpretation,(19)
just as his article Consideration and Form contained many of the
ideas later worked out in the early critical literature on rules and standards
in private law.(20)
Above all, however, today's students learn that Fuller made a third
distinct contribution to legal theory. They learn that he was the proponent
of a unique legal philosophy -- a natural law of process rather than substance.
In his 1964 book The Morality of Law,(21)
Fuller puts forward a series of formal criteria for law to meet.(22)
The difference between this argument and other attempts give content to
the ideal of the rule of law is that Fuller argues that law must
meet (or at least come a substantial way towards meeting) these criteria,
if it is to be considered law at all. Perhaps the clearest exposition of
these requirements is in the chapter in which Fuller discusses the behavior
of a bumbling hypothetical legislator called Rex, who violates each of
Fuller's principles of legality, one after another.
Rex's bungling career as legislator and judge illustrates that the attempt
to create and maintain a scheme of legal rules may miscarry in at least
eight ways; there are in this enterprise, if you will, eight distinct routes
to disaster. The first and most obvious lies in a failure to achieve rules
at all, so that every issue must be decided on an ad hoc basis. The other
routes are: (2) a failure to publicize, or at least to make available to
the affected party, the rules he is expected to observe; (3) the abuse
of retroactive legislation, which not only cannot itself guide action,
but undercuts the integrity of rules prospective in effect since it puts
them under the threat of retrospective change; (4) a failure to make rules
understandable; (5) the enactment of contradictory rules or (6) rules that
require conduct beyond the powers of the affected party; (7) introducing
such frequent changes in the rules that the subject cannot orient his action
by them; and finally, (8) a failure of congruence between the rules as
announced and their actual administration.(23)
So far, this might seem like an unexceptional list of the formal or
procedural goals associated with the ideal of the rule of law. Any such
impression is corrected when Fuller continues.
A total failure in any one of these eight directions does not simply
result in a bad system of law; it results in something that is not properly
called a legal system at all, except perhaps in the Pickwickian sense in
which a void contract can still be said to be one kind of contract.(24)
Here, as at numerous other points throughout the book, Fuller makes
clear that he sees his criteria of legality as more than a list of desiderata
culled from the particular historical experience of a few states with a
certain understanding of the rule of law. Instead, he claims that these
criteria are part of the very definition of law.(25)
Finally, he argues that the obligation to obey law depends on the same
criteria.
Certainly there can be no rational ground for asserting that a man can
have a moral obligation to obey a legal rule that does not exist, or is
kept secret from him, or that came into existence only after he had acted,
or was unintelligible, or was contradicted by another rule of the same
system, or commanded the impossible, or changed every minute. It may not
be impossible for a man to obey a rule that is disregarded by those charged
with its administration, but at some point obedience becomes futile--as
futile, in fact, as casting a vote that will never be counted.(26)
Is this point commentary or corollary? The answer, I think is the latter.
Fuller is saying that law is (and must be) defined as a concept by the
same criteria that cause it to give rise to obligation. The attraction
of this project is that it appears to offer a third pole in the debate
between positivism and natural law.(27)
The natural lawyer argues that there are universal norms of morality to
which legal systems must conform if they are to be truly "law."(28)
The positivist argues that this confuses fact with value, that the question
of what the law is should not be confused with the question of what the
law should be. "Whether it be or not be is one enquiry. Whether it
be or not be conformable to an assumed standard is another enquiry."(29)
Fuller's response to this stereotyped debate was similar to Hart and Sacks's
response to the corrosive power of legal realism.(30)
Like them, he realized the difficulty of putting forward a set of universal
substantive normative criteria for law to meet. Searching for an
uncontroversial basis upon which to build a theory, but convinced that
any general normative principle could be attacked as partial, controversial
or uselessly vague, Fuller turned instead to a jurisprudence of process.(31)
Hart and Sacks's Legal Process materials(32)
were famous in part because they made exactly the same turn. In Fuller's
case however, the postulated procedural values, publication, proactive
application, clarity, possibility and so on, were supposed to be universal,
to apply beyond the boundaries and political traditions of the United States.
Where did they come from?
In both his debates over the interpretation of a single word of a statute
and his debates about the concept of law itself, Fuller's theoretical touchstone
is the notion of purpose. The root definition he gives of law is "the
enterprise of subjecting human behavior to rules."(33)
With this enterprise in mind, Fuller believes that he can deduce the eight
tenets of procedural natural law described above.
As the sociologist Simmel has observed, there is a kind of reciprocity
between government and the citizen with respect to the observance of rules.
Government says to the citizen in effect, "These are the rules we
expect you to follow. If you follow them, you have our assurance that they
are the rules that will be applied to your conduct." When this bond
of reciprocity is finally and completely ruptured by government, nothing
is left on which to ground the citizen's duty to observe the rules.(34)
Thus the definition of law, the obligation to obey the law and the internal
procedural morality of law are deduced from a "kind of reciprocity"
between government and citizen. This is not an explicit social contract
theory of the kind offered by Locke. Nevertheless, Fuller is clearly adopting
the structure and rhetoric of the social contract in his analysis of the
bonds between government and citizen. Breach of the bond of reciprocity
ends the obligation of the citzen to obey the commands of the state. It
is from this implict contract -- immanent in the very idea of law
-- that the eight criteria of legality are to be deduced. Yet Fuller's
own work on contracts makes his eight criteria surprising, to say the least.
Fuller is one of the greatest American exponents of the idea that there
are no trans-social, formal criteria of validity for private contracts.
He argued that it was impossible to deduce contractual ground rules from
the mere notion of binding agreement and exchange -- impossible, absent
some particular social context. How then could he believe that such criteria
and such ground rules could be deduced from and for the social contract
itself? Why did he not apply the insights of his own private law contract
theory to his grand edifice of procedural natural law?
Mistake?: Three hypotheses present themselves. The first is that
of random error. Fuller simply did not see the apparent inconsistency.
I will call this the "mistake" theory, and reject it more or
less out of hand. Fuller was brilliant and highly self-critical. What's
more, unlike many theorists who write entirely about law in the abstract
or about law in some concrete context, Fuller's work consistently and commendably
links the various levels of abstraction. To put it another way, Fuller
is probably the least likely legal theorist of his generation to
fail to see the connections between some understanding of private law and
some more general account of the concept of law itself. Such a charge could
much more easily be levelled against someone like Hans Kelsen. Indeed,
that is one of the reasons why Fuller's work continues to be of interest,
while Kelsen's increasingly seems to be an historical oddity -- an answer
to a question based on an epistemological confusion, directed towards a
debate upon whose outcome nothing depended. Admittedly, I cannot disprove
the "mistake" theory but it seems to me to be a deeply unsatisfying
explanation.
Public and Private: The second hypothesis refines the mistake
theory by adding to it the notion of ideological confusion, pressure or
denial -- in this case, denial of the homologies between public and private.
For brevity, I will call this the "denial" theory.
During Fuller's lifetime, the distinction between public and private
was one of the most politically charged issues in American law.(35)
To summarize a very complex issue very quickly, one could say that the
conceptual tools of legal realism undermined faith in the public/private
distinction, a faith that seemed a vital part of liberal political theory.
On the theoretical level, Morris Cohen's Property and Sovereignty,(36)
and Jaffe's(37) and Hale's(38)
articles on the law of contract all seemed to show that rules of private
law could be seen as regulatory, that contract law could be seen as the
delegation of public power to private actors and that even the most "private"
activities could be described so as to invoke the public interest.(39)
On the level of practical politics, most of the agencies of the New Deal
could not neatly be classified in terms of the classical liberal dichotomy
of public and private. What for example, was the Tennesee Valley Authority?
At the high point of this movement, in the case of Shelley v Kraemer,(40)
the Supreme Court actually accepted the argument that the mere enforcement
of private contracts by the state courts counted as state action(41)
-- a ruling that implicitly subjected every private law relationship to
constitutional scrutiny.
This background offers some strong ideological and epistemological reasons
why Fuller might not see the connection between his public and his private
jurisprudence. Whatever theoretical language we use to express the thought,
we know that societies and individuals can have beliefs or mental frameworks
so fundamental that they completely obscure connections or implications
that seem inescapable to outsiders. Even today people talk confidently
of "deregulation" as though the rules of private law were not
regulation, or chart their moral course around the words "public"
and "private" as though those terms described an unchanging geography
of social division. Did cognitive dissonance or an ideological veil keep
Fuller from seeing the connections and contradictions I have described
here? Did he think that Consideration and Form dealt with a qualitatively
different set of moral and epistemological issues than The Morality
of Law?
My reaction to this second hypothesis is not quite as dismissive as
my reaction to the mistake theory. Nevertheless, I would say that while
the denial explanation would be downright convincing if applied to some
of Fuller's contemporaries, it seems much more unlikely when applied to
him -- at least in this form. One test for this theory would be to examine
how Fuller discussed contract, property and tort. Did he see them as neutral,
private institutions, subject to none of the questions of goal and value
raised by the institutional framework of state government? The answer is
a clear "no." Fuller almost always presented private law doctrines
with reference to their "social functions." A passage discussing
consideration is characteristic.
It has sometimes been proposed that the doctrine of consideration be
"abolished." Such a step would, I believe, be unwise, and in
a broad sense even impossible.... What needs abolition is not the doctrine
of consideration but a conception of legal method which assumes that the
doctrine can be understood and applied without reference to the ends it
serves.(42)
A second and more particular test would be whether Fuller saw private
contract, itself, as the natural form of promise and exchange or as a morally
contingent type of private legislation? Again, the answer is clear.
If A and B sign articles of partnership we have little difficulty in
seeing the analogy between their act and that of a legislature. But if
A contracts to buy a ton of coal from B for eight dollars, it seems absurd
to conceive of this act as species of private law making. This is only
because we have come to view the distribution of goods through private
contract as a part of the order of nature, and we forget that it is only
one of several possible ways of accomplishing the same general objective.
Coal does not have to be bought and sold; it can be distributed by the
decrees of a dictator, or of an elected rationing board. When we allow
it to be bought and sold by private agreement, we are, within certain limits,
allowing individuals to set their own legal relations with regard to coal.(43)
These do not sound like the words of someone who thinks of private law
in a totally different way than public law. At least as stated, the denial
theory is unconvincing. Later I will suggest that elements of it could
be retained in a more complete and believable account.
The third available hypothesis deserves extended consideration. It links
Fuller's apparent change of views to the history of legal realism.
Fuller and Realism in Newgarth: In the 1930's and 1940's a number
of prominent realists turned away from realism because they believed that
it had undermined belief in the rule of law -- the last thing that one
would want to do when preparing or fighting a war with fascism. Purcell
gives an excellent account in The Crisis of Democratic Theory of
the contortions through which realists attempted to make their work consistent
with the pieties of the rule of law.(44)
In the aftermath of the Second World War, the process continued. Jerome
Frank, the author of Law and the Modern Mind,(45)
had explained fixation on precedent by invoking Freudian theory and the
subconscious desire for an intellectual father who would take painful choice
out of our hands. Frank's judicial psychology seems to be premised on a
pervasive ethical relativism; that, after all, is what gives the question
of judicial method its "bite." Yet by 1948 he was saying "I
do not understand how any decent man today can refuse to adopt, as the
basis of modern civilization, the fundamental principles of natural law,
relative to human conduct, as stated by Thomas Aquinas."(46)
Fuller himself exhibited a lifelong relationship of attraction to and
repulsion from realist doctrines.(47) This
profound ambivalence is nowhere as clearly indicated as in his famous set
of hypothetical cases set in Newgarth, of which the ruse of the Speluncean
Explorers is the best known.(48) Fuller
uses the judges of these imaginary cases to personify various legal philosophies.
There is a bumbling, pompous formalist chief justice called Truepenny,
a relentless positivist called Keen, and an agonized and indecisive justice
who Fuller, in what appears to be an interesting piece of stereotyping,
calls Justice Tatting. But the most fully realised characters, those whose
opinions read as though they come from profound, if antithetical convictions,
are Justices Foster and Handy.
Justice Handy is an arch-realist -- a realist so exaggerated that at
times one suspects he is being deliberately parodied so as to remove any
residual attraction that Fuller might have felt towards realist ideas.
Yet Fuller is too meticulous a thinker to deal entirely in stereotype and
there are moments when he seems to take pleasure in having Handy attack
the pieties uttered by the judge who seems closest to his own purposive
vision of law -- Justice Foster. Handy sees the law as a matter of practical
politics, he constantly flaunts the conventions of the judicial role and
delights in puncturing the constructs with which his earnest colleague
Foster attempts to defend a middle ground between raw politics on the one
hand and formalism on the other. Fuller himself offers the following interesting
authorial caution about Handy.
If there is an element of caricature in all of the judicial opinions
in this volume, in the case of Mr. Justice Handy the matter goes beyond
a mere exaggeration of recognizable traits. It would be difficult to find
a counterpart for him on any of our courts. Some may feel that a happier
day will dawn in Newgarth when he has been impeached and deprived of his
office. But if he is indeed the Evil One disguised in a black robe, we
need to become acquainted with his wiles so that we may recognize them
and take steps to protect ourselves against the temptations he throws in
our way.(49)
I do not think I am stretching the interpretation in saying that the
actual opinions contained in the book evidence a certain shameful temptation
as well as the more proper feeling of disapproval shown by this
quotation. Throughout the opinions, Fuller has Handy repeatedly tease the
more serious Foster -- tempting him with a realist world of practical politics.
After one of the many rebukes hurled Handy's way by the Chief Justice for
bringing into the record facts that are not properly before the court,
Handy defends himself sardonically by noting that he has "the only
mind on the court impure enough to be influenced by the legally irrelevant."(50)
Then he offers some second thoughts about Foster's susceptibility.
On reflection, I am not so sure of my brother Foster, and perhaps for
his sake I ought to desist. It may startle my hearers for me to say so,
but in many ways I feel myself closer to Foster than to anyone else on
this court. If he could only rip off that metaphysical jacket he has put
on himself, and gain a little more freedom of action, I think we might
get along very well indeed.(51)
The main axes along which Foster and Handy do battle, and along which
Fuller's ambivalence about realism asserted itself were the tensions between
fact and norm on the one hand and form and substance on the other. All
of Fuller's hypothetical cases show that one cannot conceive of
the law as purely form or purely substance, purely 'is' or purely 'ought.'
In both of these pairs, one pole both requires and denies the other. Thus,
in the Speluncean Explorers, Handy argues that "government is a human
affair" and laments the legal tendency to analyze a situation "until
all the life and juice have gone out of it and we have left a handful of
dust."(52) In place of this tendency
towards form and formal analysis, Handy argues for close attention to substance,
to popular will and practical politics. But even an arch-realist like Handy
acknowledges that there are
a few fundamental rules of the game that must be accepted if the game
is to go on at all. I would include among these the rules relating to the
conduct of elections, the appointment of public officials, and the term
during which an office is held. Here some restraints on discretion and
dispensation, some adherence to form, some scruple for what does and does
not fall within the rule, is, I concede essential.(53)
With Fuller's characteristic love of nested insights, Handy then shows
how problematic a task it is to pick these 'foundational' rules. Having
gulled the unwary reader by referring to apparently uncontentious procedural
rules of election law, Handy adds, "perhaps the area of basic principle
should be expanded to include certain other rules such as those designed
to preserve the free civilmoign system."(54)
We must have both form and substance, and Handy wants to restrict our ideas
of formal justice to those "few fundamental rules of the fame that
must be accepted if the game is to go on at all." But which rules
exactly are those? Generations of students have wondered aloud just what
exactly "the free civilmoign system" is, only to discover that
one of their classmates said confidently "it must be property rights"
while another thought it to be human rights and the third, the institutional
framework of the market.
One might conclude from this that, long before Jacques Derrida and "dangerous
supplementarity," Lon Fuller was capable of showing us the inherent
instability of any attempt to reconcile two concepts that both deny and
depend on each other. In this case, the concepts were formal and substantive
justice.(55) Fuller was adept at demonstrating
that the realists would have to put some limit on the idea that judges
act as practical politicians,(56) and yet
would be unable to justify those limits in any uncontentious way wihout
resorting to the same kind of formalism and essentialism they themselves
had criticized. Yet he did not exempt his own alter ego from the
same criticism.(57)
To put a complicated intellectual biography very tersely indeed, I would
say that Fuller was never free of ambivalence towards realist ideas, but
that he became more and more hesitant about them as he got older. Although
all of the legal philosophies Fuller described conflicted with each other,
realism posed a particularly acute challenge to basic assumptions about
the legal system. The later Fuller seemed both to assert that a judge's
legal philosophy played a role even in easy cases, and that conflicts between
different visions of the law would be mediated by the conventions of professional
life.
To be sure, different judges entertain different philosophies of law
and these philosophies may affect their treatment of even the most technical
seeming questions. In actual life, however, these differences are usually
softened by a spirit of democratic tolerance, controlled by adherence to
a common professional tradition, and bridged in some degree by a felt but
unexpressed conviction that the whole of truth can never be contained in
a single point of view.(58)
But it is hard to accept this attractive picture of professional reconciliation
in a spirit of democratic tolerance when the conflicts between paradigms
or philosophies are absolutely basic. Is the apparent conflict I have described
in this article such a conflict? We must first get a sense of how the social
contract would look if Fuller's private law jurisprudence was applied to
it. More generally, I will explore the extent to which "formal"
criteria have been understood as necessary to further the principle of
autonomy, in both public and private contracts.
II
The Social Contract as Private Contract: The Relationship
of Form to Autonomy
As I said before, Fuller's most famous contribution to the contracts
literature was the Reliance Interest article he wrote with Perdue.
But there are several other pieces that express his own ideas about the
relationship of form to substance in the law of contract. Most notable
among these, is the 1941 article in the Columbia Law Review entitled Consideration
and Form.(59) In a series of numbered
paragraphs, a style reminiscent of Wittgenstein to modern eyes, Fuller
lays out his basic ideas about contract liability with extraordinary clarity
and precision. His focus is on the subtle, reflexive connections between
the substantive values of contract law and its formal requirements. Like
most contract theorists, Fuller stresses the importance of the promotion
of private autonomy.
Among the basic conceptions of contract law the most pervasive and indispensable is the principle of private autonomy... The principle of private autonomy may be translated into terms of the will theory by saying that this principle merely means that the will of the parties sets their legal relations.(60)
Thus our understanding of the goal(61) of contract law has been seen in American legal thought to dictate our theory of how contracts should be interpreted and enforced. But this linkage of contract with the will theory brings a suite of problems in its wake.
When this principle is stated in this way certain consequences may seem
to follow from it: (1) that the law must concern itself solely with the
actual inner intention of the promisor; (2) that the minds of the parties
must "meet" at one instant of time before a contract can result;
(3) that the law has no power to fill gaps in an agreement and is helpless
to deal with contingencies unforeseen by the parties; and even (4) that
the promisor must be free to change his mind at any time, since it is his
will which sets the rule. Since these consequences of the will theory are
regarded as unacceptable, the theory is assumed to be refuted by the fact
that it entails them.(62)
One of Fuller's purposes in writing Consideration and Form was
to argue that the principle of autonomy could be maintained without recourse
to the definitional fragility of will theory.(63)
Thus with regard to the first point noted above, for example, he argued
that the "objective" interpretation of contracts was not only
compatible with the principle of private autonomy, it could actually
be seen as a corollary of that principle by setting up a commonly
understood structure in which autonomous private parties could pursue their
own ends more efficaciously.(64) Fuller
dealt with some of the other problems with the will theory by arguing that
private autonomy had a legitimately restricted ambit.(65)
He also tried, unsuccessfully in my view, to minimize the anomalous nature
of the reliance interest -- both in damages and as an independent ground
of contract liability.(66) Finally, Fuller
pointed out that the supposed reasons for insisting on "consideration
and form" as a basis for contracts would differ markedly depending
on the social context, the power disparity between the parties, the nature
of the transaction and the type of interests involved.
Consideration and Form thus attempts to separate form from autonomy.
Fuller criticises the notion that contract law is a formal structure deduced
from a principle of autonomy and applied in idealized contractual relationships
abstracted from their social settings. The article does not give up the
principle of private autonomy, but rather argues that we should attend
to the principle rather than to the formal construct with which it had
become associated -- the will theory of contract. At the same time, Fuller
argued that the principle was not all-embracing, that it must sometimes
give way to other goals and, in any event, that it can be better pursued
through a flexible and context-sensitive law of contract.(67)
Thus -- like all of Fuller's work -- the article declares the necessity
of a dialectical inquiry, focusing both on the purposes of a body of law
and on the concrete locations in which it is to be applied.
So Fuller was interested in the notion that autonomy is the primary
goal of contract law, and that the formal requirements of contract can
be deduced from this goal. In the realm of private contracts some of his
greatest work consisted of an exploration of the difficulties with this
idea. How do these difficulties apply to the social contract?
Parallel Problems: At first glance, social contract theories
too, seem both rooted in and rhetorically constructed around a vision of
private autonomy.(68) Both types of contract
offer a narrative structure in which the chronology of acceptance of the
contractual regime marks the progress away from brute compulsion and necessity
and towards freedom and individualism. Maine's summary of classical liberal
historiography in the aphorism that we are moving 'from status to contract'(69)
is paralleled in social contract theory in the idea that we move from a
mythical pre-social state of nature to the realm of civilization, government
and respect for private property. In both, the attraction is the idea that
we are entering a realm where social arrangements are not incompatible
with freedom, because it is the affected parties who bind themselves to
their own prior will -- either with laws or with the private legislation
of the contract.
Interpretation: Given these similarities, it is not surprising that the same sort of problems Fuller describes for the will theory are commonly understood to beset social contract theory. After all, a meeting of the minds between the contracting parties in the social contract seems even more unlikely than in the ticket cases.(70) Even if such a meeting of the minds is conclusively assumed, what is its content? The state is in the anomalous position of being both called into being by, and responsible for interpreting, the social contract. How is it to do so? Suppose that we assume that the purpose of the social contract is to maximize autonomy and that this purpose necessitates some kind of "will theory" of interpretation. What practical consequences does this entail?
In the United States this -- or at least a closely cognate question
-- has been most vigorously argued in the debates over originalism.(71)
What is the proper method for interpreting the foundational moment of the
society? The most popular proponents of originalism began, as did the classicists,
by proposing something very like a simple version of will theory with its
accompanying focus on intent. Thus, for example, in 1986 Robert
Bork declared his aim "to demonstrate that original intent is the
only legitimate basis for constitutional decision making."(72)
The Framers are the the authors of the constitutional compact to which
the people agreed. By binding ourselves to their intentions about the structure
and language they lay down, we remain free.
This idea of interpretation, of course, runs into all the problems of
the subjective theory of intent under will theory. (It is striking however
to find that the parallel is almost never mentioned.) In 1988 Henry Monaghan
remonstrated with those among his fellow originalists who had adopted "intentionalism"
for providing "an easy mark for critics of originalism."(73)
Again, as with private contracts, the tendency seems to have been to move
away from the simple intentionalist vision towards a more general, socially-based
vision of interpretation.(74) Thus, by
1991, Bork was arguing that "[n]o even moderately sophisticated originalist"
believes the Constitution should be interpreted according to "the
subjective intent of the Framers."(75)
Instead, Bork offered the idea of "original understanding,"
thus moving the interpretive focus onto the community in much the same
way as the objective theory of contractual interpretation had done.(76)
Bork argues that this notion of interpretation is entirely consistent with
the notion of individual autonomy under a democracy.(77)
His arguments are almost identical to those Fuller offers in Consideration
and Form. Indeed both use the same example (interpretation according
to the private intentions of legislators) to attack the excesses of intentionalism
and the same justification (freedom within a commonly understood structure,
collectively assented to) for the compatibility of "objective"
interpretation with private autonomy.
Form: In private law, Fuller offered a resolutely contextual
account of the relationship of form to substance. "The need for investing
a particular transaction with some legal formality will depend on the extent
to which the guaranties that the formality would afford are rendered superfluous
by forces native to the situation out of which the transaction arises."(78)
Fuller goes on to give the example of formalities designed to make the
parties think about what they are doing. As usual he takes a purposive
view of such requirements, saying that the need for them depends on whether
"the factual situation, innocent of any legal remolding, tends to
bring about the desired circumspective frame of mind."(79)
Thus, we have our criterion for the utility of form; is the purpose that
a formal requirement serves already accomplished by the context? How would
this criterion apply to the social contract, to the edifice of procedural
natural law that Fuller finds immanent within the reciprocity between government
and citizen?
The immediate answer seems to be that such a view of the relationship
of form to context would tend to undermine both the epistemological basis
for and the uncompromising statement of Fuller's eight criteria of legality.
Instead of arguing that the concept of law itself contains the prohibition
against retroactivity, we would have to flesh out the purposes that such
a prohibition is designed to serve and then examine the particular society,
the particular form of government and the particular context in which retroactivity
was being considered. For example, imagine a society in which abuses of
private power were at least as much to be feared as abuses of state power.
In this society, let us postulate that there are enormous corporations,
disproportionately well represented in the legislature and the legal system,
who are capable of seeding the tax laws with loopholes of which they can
then take advantage. The tax burden would consequently fall on the individual
citizen who was unable, individually or as a member of a group, to wield
equivalent influence. In additition, imagine also that because of information
costs, it is disproportionately harder for individual citizens to discover
the import of particular technical rules. In this imaginary society, the
consequences of specific legislative deals might only become apparent in
hindsight.
In such a society, we might imagine that retroactive taxation of "windfall
profits" would seem like a lesser evil, perhaps even the lesser of
two evils. At the very least, it would not seem so clearly a violation
of one of the criteria of legality. Substantive differences in power would
have undermined or at least gravely weakened the reasons for the formal
prohibition -- in exactly the way that Fuller describes in Consideration
and Form.(80) Admittedly, Fuller does
say that one would have to take a holistic assessment of his eight criteria,
and apparently agrees that one deviation from legality would not enough
to undermine a legal system. For the most part, however, Fuller does not
discuss the social conditions that would render his eight criteria of validity
superfluous. Yet this is the kind of contextual and purposive discussion
of formal requirements that he had advocated so persuasively in his writing
on private contracts.(81)
In Fuller's jurisprudential theory, by contrast, the very concept of
law itself is loaded with a series of conclusory (but contentious) assumptions
that make this situational examination superfluous, if not pointless.(82)
It is as if Consideration and Form argued that a contract without
adequate consideration could never be valid because, by definition, it
would not be a contract.
This brings me back to the question "why the difference?"
As the introduction to this section suggests, the difference in Fuller's
attitude towards form in private contracts and in the social contract may
turn on contrasting attitudes towards autonomy. In private law, Fuller
could hardly have been accused of being unsympathetic to concerns about
autonomy. He called it "the most basic and indispensable" principle
among the basic conceptions of contract law. But Fuller argued that "will
theory is only a figurative way of expressing the principle of private
autonomy," pointed out that there were important limits on the application
of the principle and warned us against confusing the principle with the
metonymic formal construct with which it had become associated. When that
metonymic formal construct is "the rule of law" rather than will
theory, Fuller's resolve seems to weaken.
Notice for example, that in The Morality of Law Fuller describes
law as "the enterprise of subjecting human conduct to the governance
of rules"(83) and that all
of his eight criteria are centrally concerned with a vision of law as an
affair of rules rather than, say, of standards or goals. Why? Part of the
reason lies in the type of reciprocity that he envisions between
government and citizen. This vision of reciprocity protects a narrow vision
of freedom of action, of autonomy. As Fuller put it "government says
to the citizen in effect, 'These are the rules we expect you to follow.
If you follow them, you have our assurance that they are the rules that
will be applied to your conduct.'"(84)
In part, this argument appeals to the notion of justified reliance. But
as the other stages in the progress of Rex's débâcle unfolds,
it becomes clear that an even more important value to be protected is the
realm of freedom that is left to the individual inside the boundaries laid
down by the clear commands of a rule-making state. Justice Foster's opinion
in The Speluncean Explorers sounds the same themes, and links them
explicitly to the social contract between the naturally free citizen and
the limited state.(85)
It is important to remember that Fuller is telling us that we can deduce
normative conclusions from the nature of the legal system, a position
very different from his claim about the very idea of private contracts.
Yet the norms he deduces from the concept of law are norms of formality
and procedure. Fuller seems to be incorporating the concerns of classical
liberalism into his idea of law. One cannot be sure, but to me it seems
reasonable to believe that Fuller is assuming that the trans-social goal
of law is the restraint of a potentially oppressive state and the guidance
of a citizenry seeking assurances of complete autonomy within the sphere
of non-proscribed conduct. The cords used to bind the state are also the
guide ropes for the citizenry and this legal cordage should be, indeed
must be, woven from rules.(86) Thus,
Fuller believes that his formal and procedural requirements can be deduced
from the concept of a legal system whereas other goals -- democratic decision-making,
protection of human rights, the enhancement of social welfare or the promotion
of economic efficiency -- are merely contentious external normative desiderata,
each competing for our affections.
Why should we assume that the citizen is better guided, or the state
better restrained, by rules and formality? There is a strong legal realist
counter-argument to this position which runs something like this. In a
society where there are barriers of class, price, time or expertise to
the acquisition of information, standards may be a better guide to behaviour
than rules. The argument depends on a number of contentious assumptions:
in particular, that standards will be based on relative community norms
such as "good faith in the trade" and that the individual who
needs to predict state action under the standard is also a member of the
community. Under those two assumptions, the individual in a regime of ostensibly
vague standards may find it easier to "know the law" than the
individual who lives in a world of ostensibly clear rules, rules that,
in practice, are unknown and counter-intuitive in their complexity.
There are other variations on this argument. Earlier, I quoted Fuller
himself accepting the argument that excessive regard for formality led
to the courts "torturing" legal doctrine and that "the `non-technical'
considerations which really motivated" decisions should be accepted
and recognised.(87) Failure to do so, Fuller
suggested, would lead to unpredictability of exactly the kind that the
Morality of Law abhors, as the judges strove to escape from the
narrow enclosure in which they were penned. Thus, the realists, with their
skepticism about rules and their attention to policy, were actually making
"the judge a more tractable and predictable animal."(88)
Yet when it comes to the larger jurisprudential stage of The Morality
of Law, the idea that rule-skepticism might increase the predictability
of the legal system, and hence the "knowable domain of freedom"
of the individual, seems entirely absent. Instead, we have returned to
a type of classical liberalism in which autonomy is conclusively presumed
to be the most important value and rules are conclusively presumed to be
the mechanism by which autonomy is to be assured.
Part of the reason may be that the stakes of the discussion have changed.
It is important and, to some, shocking, to challenge the ambit, formal
realisability and conceptual essentialism of the principle of private autonomy
in contract law. Nevertheless, the political stakes do not seem to be as
high as they are in the discussion of the rule of law. Many flavors of
liberal state theory take it as definitionally true that abuses of public
power are more to be feared than abuses of private power, that rules constrain
governments more than standards and -- perhaps most significantly of all
-- that autonomy is more legitimately the concern of the state than equality.
If Fuller was to be as skeptical of these definitional pieties as he was
of those of will theory, the result would be more sweeping in its imaginative
transformation of the state than Section 90 or Hoffman v. Red Owl.(89)
In private law, Fuller can loose the surly bonds of liberal political theory.
But writing as "a jurisprude" he finds those bonds to be inescapable.
Consent In a famous passage, Hume criticized the notion of consent
behind social contract theories -- arguing that it was so attenuated as
to mean nothing at all. "We may as well assert that a man, by remaining
in a vessel, freely consents to the dominion of the master, though he was
carried on board while asleep, and must leap into the ocean and perish,
the moment he leaves her."(90) To
use the words of a modern political theorist, "consent theory's big
gun turns out to be of woefully small caliber."(91)
In private law, a similar question has been debated over the issue of
the enforceability of "standard form contracts" although, once
again, the parallel is hardly ever mentioned. In a famous article on the
subject, Professor Slawson argues that if standard form contracts are to
be enforceable, their enforceability cannot rest on consent.(92)
In most cases, such consent is entirely absent, except as a legal fiction.
Instead, such contracts should only be enforceable if their substantive
terms meet criteria of justice and fairness. This also seems to me to be
the clear implication of Fuller's contract law jurisprudence. In fact,
it is fair to say that private law theory in general has
paid fruitful, if intermittent, attention to the issue of whether consent
is best seen as a psychological fact (meeting of the minds), as a substantive
theory of the justice of outcomes, a capacious conceptual box designed
to hold the values of the moment, or as some other, more complicated, amalgam
of social practice and moral obligation.(93)
When it comes to the rule of law, Fuller's notion of consent seems a
thin one, to say the least. He picks as an illustrative case study the
rules made by a monarch. While Rex fails in many ways to make law, the
failure of democracy is not one of them. A failure to "achieve rules"
means that no law is ever made, as does the failure to issue rules that
are internally consistent, comprehensible and capable of being followed.
Retroactive rules, rules that change with undue frequency and rules which
are not congruent with official behaviour also fail to achieve the status
of law. In each of these cases, Fuller's argument stems from the "reciprocity
between government and citizen."(94)
Yet the power of citizens to make, to accept or reject the rules -- whether
directly or through representatives -- is no part of this reciprocity.
Thus we have the apparently anomalous result that a theory built on the
language of the social contract still manages to rank legal form higher
than democracy.
To understand how Fuller gets to this point it is necessary to step
back from this particular argument for a moment, and examine his method
of generating "the morality that makes law possible." Remember,
Fuller claims that the eight criteria are more than mere desiderata
for efficiency or equity. They can be deduced from the very definition
of law, norms that can be deduced from facts, a procedure that most philosophers
since Hume have understood to be impossible.(95)
Fuller argues that his criteria comes from the very definition of law,
because the very definition of law includes certain uncontentious
purposes and achievement of those puposes constitutes the good. In the
book After Virtue, Alasdair MacIntyre gives a good example of this
kind of argument in his attempt to show that values can be deduced from
facts, provided only that the factual construct is one that has an accepted
telos or purpose.(96) His two examples
are "a watch" and "a farmer." He claims that the mere
definition of these two terms provides us with normative arguments about
them.
[T]hese arguments are valid because of the special character of a watch
and a farmer. Such concepts are functional concepts; that is to say, we
define both 'watch' and 'farmer' in terms of the purpose or function which
a watch or a farmer are characteristically expected to serve. It follows
that the concept of a watch cannot be defined independently of the concept
of a good watch nor the concept of a farmer independently of that of a
good farmer; and that the criterion of something's being a watch and the
criterion of something's being a good watch -- and so also for farmer and
all other functional concepts -- are not independent of each other.
Now clearly both sets of criteria -- as is evidenced by the examples given
in the last paragraph -- are factual. Hence any argument which moves from
premises which assert that the appropriate criteria are satisfied to a
conclusion which asserts that 'This is a good such-and-such', where 'such-and-such'
picks out an item by a functional concept, will be a valid argument which
moves from factual premises to an evaluative conclusion. Thus, we may safely
assert that, if some amended version of the 'No "ought conclusion
from "is" premises' principle is to hold good, it must exclude
arguments involving functional concepts from its scope.(97)
MacIntyre gives as an example the argument that from the mere fact that
a watch is too heavy to carry or grossly inaccurate we could deduce
the normative conclusion that it was a bad watch. Fuller ups the definitional
stakes. Based on a largely implicit set of assumptions about the functions
of law and the telos of the legal relationship between state and
citizen, he deduces his criteria and makes them definitive. To use MacIntyre's
example, it is as if we said that a watch which is slow or heavy is not
a watch at all. The problem with this procedure however, is that even these
supposedly uncontentious "functional concepts" dissolve back
into contingent facts and contentious purposes. Fashion watches, Dali's
watches, and clunky Soviet army watches, environmentalist farmers, agribusiness
tycoons, and crofters; all give evidence of the fact that the norms of
superior watch and farmer-ness are not built into the concepts themselves.
What is true of watches and farmers is even more true of law.
The only way that arguments like this can survive is to pick implicit
values that are either vague enough or reassuringly familiar enough to
survive prolonged scrutiny. Thus, when Fuller tries to make his stand between
positivism and natural law, he relies on the familiar notion of the state
as law giver. There are many norms one could see embodied in the tradition
of the rule of law, or deduced from the social contract. One could imagine
that heteronomy, or solidarity, or equality, or democratic self-governance
is the value coded into law's telos, the value on which the reciprocity
between citizen and state depends. But these arguments are a little more
complex, a little more obviously subject to challenge. The need to produce
an apparently uncontentious set of functional norms draws Fuller away from
the complexity he had demonstrated so well in private law. Rather than
a reciprocal relationship of form and substance, a polyphonic chorus of
values and a sophisticated understanding of the ways in which standards
can constrain tighter than rules, we return to a world in which
law must be an affair of rules, rules which produce order for the
society and (bounded) autonomy for the citizen. We can deduce these formal
requisites from the nature of law as a reciprocal relationship between
government and citizen. We have come full circle. Lon Fuller has returned
to the will theory of contract.
How might things have been different? I noted at the beginning of this
section that consent -- supposedly the raison d'être of social
contract theories -- is in fact one of their weakest points. In private
law, the obvious difficulty of explaining mass contracts to which there
is no real alternative has driven many contracts theorists to argue that
enforceability can only depend on the substantive justice of the provisions
of the contract.(98) This is perhaps the
most revealing parallel between private law and state theory. Had Fuller
followed this insight when he came to The Morality of Law he would
have been driven to acknowledge that -- by his own premises -- his formal
criteria, his concentration on rule-form and procedural requirement, could
never supply the basis for the obligation to obey the law.(99)
He might have been driven to the conclusion that there was no general basis
for the obligation to obey the law. This, after all, would have been the
logical outcome of his contracts scholarship. Alternatively, Fuller might
have been driven to offer a theory of substantive justice. Instead of claiming
a third position in the debate between natural law and positivism. Fuller
would have joined the natural law side -- at least in the sense that one
can say little of interest about legal philosophy without entering into
normative debate. What's more, Fuller would have made the normative turn
without an unquestioning adherence to the definitional pieties of liberal
legalism. If we go by his contract jurisprudence, we have to imagine him
rejecting the idea that private power is qualitatively different from public
power, that state oppression is always more to be feared than private inequality,
that autonomy is the supreme goal of the legal system and that contract
-- whether social or private -- is merely the enforcement of preexisting
consent.
Conclusion: It is hard to imagine exactly what kind of theory
would have emerged if Fuller had taken the turn I describe here. I imagine
an odd combination of Rawls and Hale -- a liberalism with a large measure
of skeptical legal realism. If that picture seems strange, it can only
be because we have kept the two halves of our contractarian traditions
separate, despite their logical, normative and epistemological similarities.
In private law, a watered-down legal realism has become our orthodoxy.
Yet when we turn to jurisprudence, or political theory, the skepticism
about form, about definitional reasoning and about the limits of private
power, seems distinctly muted. A large portion of contemporary political
philosophy is enamoured of contractarian rhetoric. Grand contractarian
schemes attempt to deduce the structure of a just society from hypothetical
choices made behind a veil of ignorance, or to anchor the nightwatchman
state in autonomy and contract. Yet one will search political theory in
vain for references to the rich private law literature examining the difficulties
in applying the principle of private autonomy without some contentious
theory of the person, or some controversial invocation of substantive values.
In constitutional law, originalists debate whether the constitution
should be interpreted according to the theory of original intent or original
understanding, yet one looks in vain for a comparison to the analogous
debate in contract law. Were contracts only formed when there was an actual
meeting of the minds, or could a court legitimately look to the "objective"
meaning of the parties' statements? Was will theory really the corollary
of a belief in private autonomy or was it merely a partial and figurative
representation of that principle? The conceptual apartheid maintained between
the public and the private half of the contractarian tradition is sometimes
breached, of course, but the episodic quality of these breaches makes the
narrow orthodoxy of political theory and constitutional scholarship all
the more visible.
I would close with one final suggestion. Looking back on the largely
unresolved tension between the two sides of Fuller's work, I have been
moved to the suggestion that Fuller's work has been so influential because
of, rather than in spite of, the conflict. Whether conservative, liberal
or radical, some of the most vigorous and interesting legal scholarship
in the nineteen eighties breached the apartheid I have just described,
but in the opposite direction -- starting in the details of doctrinal analysis
or the problems revealed by legal realism and then moving outwards to liberal
social theory. Writers as different as Charles Fried, Roberto Unger, Duncan
Kennedy, Cass Sunstein and Bruce Ackerman have produced scholarship that
could be read this way. Kennedy produces a Fuller-like analysis of form
and substance and then asks whether there is an aesthetic connection between
arguments for "standards" and altruistic political positions
that challenge the framework of classical liberalism. Unger takes Fuller's
ideas about the interpretation of legal rules and asks if they do not undermine
liberal political theory. Fried's work on contracts seeks to reconstruct
a particular view of contractual obligation, and to protect both it and
the principle of private autonomy which it expresses, from a utilitarian,
realist, social welfare type of analysis. Ackerman's work on liberal state
theory and Sunstein's application of legal realist baseline analysis to
the first amendment, rather than to private law, do much the same thing.
The list could be extended and quibbled over, of course. Obviously there
were other factors at work, and the extent of direct conscious influence
is not as great as this idealist litany might suggest.(100)
Neverthless, the conclusion I am left with is that Fuller's work provided
a jumping-off place for so many scholars precisely because of its
unresolved tensions. In the end, Fuller's rôle in legal scholarship
may have been to bring the two sides of these contractarian traditions
to a high, but ultimately inconsistent, level of sophistication and then
to leave them there, nagging the next generation.
It remains to be seen whether the legal realist analysis of market, freedom, rules and form will ultimately wreak some greater transformation in the tradition of liberal political theory than that represented by the conceptual itches of a few law professors. In this, as in many other things, the work of Lon Fuller presents us with a momentary ability to imagine how things could have been otherwise.
1. 0 Professor of Law, American University. This essay was written while I was a Visiting Professor of Law at Harvard Law School. The Harvard Law School Research Fund provided generous support.
2. 0 Lon L. Fuller, American Legal Realism, 82 U. Pa. L. Rev 429, 443 (1934).
3. 0 Lon L. Fuller, The Morality of Law 39 (rev. ed. 1969).
4. 0 I take the phrase from my colleague Mark Hager who originally used it to refer to the implicit messages of legal concepts, or the metaphors of social thought, rather than of legal thinkers. "Despite the demise of formalism, however, legal concepts continue to exert their force as they have always done, as metaphors, symbols, images, and visions of social existence. This is what I call the "iconic" dimension of argument, the way in which a particular image stands for a whole cluster of interrelated ideas. As example of iconic images in social thought we might list: Leviathan, the Invisible Hand, the Polis, the Atomized Individual, and the Single-Office-and-Factory." Mark Hager, Bodies Politic: The Progressive History of Organizational "Real Entity" Theory, 50 U. Pitt. L. R. 575, 576 (1989). Legal thinkers and judges sometimes also have this quality. Regardless of the justice of the depiction, Cardozo's name evokes a particular style of legal reasoning in which sweeping (progressive) change is produced without fanfare from a virtuoso manipulation of traditional legal materials. Langdell's name conjures up opinions about science, pedagogy and legal thought -- some of which he may never have held. In this pantheon, Lon Fuller's name brings to mind a number of propositions -- though to a smaller audience. One is the notion that it is possible to absorb the techniques of legal realism, subject them to critical scrutiny and even make (famous) use of some of them without being practically immobilised or reduced to nihilism and despair. Another, and more important one for my purposes, is that there is still a connection betwen the esoteric knowledge of the theorist of private law -- the writer on contracts, or torts or property -- and the esoteric knowledge of the social theorist, the practitioner of jurisprudence writ large. I am second to no-one in my admiration for Fuller but I believe this article demonstrates that, if these two propositions are true, they are true in a way entirely different from the received wisdom.
5. 0 By which I mean the general jurisprudence of the res publica, and the contractual arguments within it, not merely Fuller's writings on "public law" or on contracts with public entities.
6. 0 Restatement (Second) of Contracts §90 (1979).
7. 0 The literature on Fuller is rich and I have benefited from many sources. A number of works deserve particular mention. Patrick Atiyah, Book Review, 1983 Duke L.J. 669 (1983) (reviewing Kenneth I. Winston, The Principles of Social Order: Selected Essays of Lon L. Fuller (1981)) is the clearest and most penetrating analysis of the tension between Fuller's explanation of the principle of autonomy and his work on reliance. Todd Rakoff's, Fuller and Perdue's The Reliance Interest as a Work of Legal Scholarship, 1991 WIS. L REV. 203 convinced me of the keen "tactical" sense in Fuller's contracts scholarship. Robert Summer, Lon Fuller (1984) provided a wealth of useful background material. Finally, the recollections of a number of colleagues at Harvard Law School gave Fuller's words a "personal" feel they might otherwise might have lacked.
8. 0 Lon L. Fuller & Melvin Aron Eisenberg, Basic Contract Law (4th ed. 1981).
9. 0 Lon L. Fuller and William R. Perdue, Jr., The Reliance Interest in Contract Damages, 46 Yale L. J. 52 (1936-37).
10. 0 Lon L. Fuller, Williston on Contracts, 18 N.C.L. Rev. 1 (1939).
11. 0 Lon L. Fuller, Consideration and Form, 41 Colum. L. Rev. 799 (1941).
12. 0 Fuller, supra note 2, at 96.
13. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 821-22.
17. 0 Lon L. Fuller, The Problems of Jurisprudence 2-27 (temp. ed. 1949).
18. 0 Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law - A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 Harv. L. Rev. 630 (1958).
19. 0 Roberto M. Unger, Knowledge And Politics (1975) is probably the best example. For a discussion of Fuller's arguments and their role in the development of critical legal studies, see James Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Studies and Local Social Thought, 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 685, 711-12 (1985).
20. 0 Duncan Kennedy, Form and Substance in Private Law Adjudication, 89 Harv. L. Rev. 1685 (1976); Mark Kelman's book Critical Legal Studies contains the most sophisticated recent discussion of the politics of the rules/standards debate. Mark Kelman, Critical Legal Studies 13-63 (1987).
25. 0 A number of scholars have sought to reinterpret Fuller's eight principles as simply functional conditions of efficacy for the rule of law, a position that would be much more consistent with Fuller's work on private contracts. In a letter to Wolfgang Friedmann of Columbia, quoted by Professor Summers, Fuller dismissed this interpretation of his work. "In treating my principles of legality as mere conditions of efficacy you are in harmony with Hart, Dworkin, Cohen, Hughes and Summers. Nevertheless, in my humble opinion you are all wrong." Summers, supra note 6, at 37. Fuller repeated his rejection of this interpretation in the "Reply to Critics" printed as an afterword in the revised version of The Morality of Law. Fuller, supra note 2.
26. 0 Fuller, supra note 2, at 39.
27. 0 For a discussion of the "invented" quality of this debate see James Boyle, Thomas Hobbes and the Invented Tradition of Positivism: Reflections on Language, Power and Essentialism, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 383 (1987).
28. 0 See, e.g., A.P. D'Entreves, Natural Law (1970).
29. 0 John Austin, The Province of Jurisprudence Determined 184 (1954). See also Hans Kelsen, The Pure Theory of Law (1967).
30. 0 HENRY M. HART & ALBERT M. SACKS, THE LEGAL PROCESS: BASIC PROBLEMS IN THE MAKING AND APPLICATION OF LAW 3-6 (tent. ed. 1958); Gary Peller, "Neutral Principles" in the 1950's, 21 Mich. J.L. Ref. 561 (1988).
31. 0 For other examples of the turn to process in an attempt to evade the realist critique see Richard Parker, The Past of Constitutional Theory -- And its Future, 42 Ohio St. L.J. 223 (1981); James Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Social Thought, 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 685 (1985).
32. 0 Hart and Sacks, supra note 29, at 9.
33. 0 Fuller, supra note 2, at 106.
34. 0 FULLER, supra note 2, at 39-40.
35. 0 Morton Horwitz, The History of the Public/Private Distinction, 130 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1423 (1982); Duncan Kennedy, The Stages of the Decline of the Public/Private Distinction, 130 U. Pa. L. Rev. 1349 (1982).
36. 0 Morris R. Cohen, Property and Sovereignty, 13 Cornell L. Q. 8 (1927).
37. 0 Louis Jaffe, Law Making by Private Groups, 51 Harv. L. Rev. 201 (1937).
38. 0 Robert Hale, Bargaining, Duress and Economic Liberty, 43 Colum. L. Rev. 603 (1943).
39. 0 The status of this critique now is more open to question. "In the decades since, the Realist challenge to the "privateness" of contracts has been assimilated and diffused, a process aided by the incomplete nature of the Realist assault. Thus our principle vision of contract law is still one of a neutral facilitator of private volition. We understand that contract law is concerned at the periphery with the imposition of social duties, that quasi-contract governs situations where obligation attaches even in the absence of agreement, that doctrines of duress and fraud deprive the contracting reprobate of benefits unfairly extorted." Clare Dalton, An Essay in the Deconstruction of Contract Doctrine, 94 Yale L.J. 997, 1014 (1985).
42. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 824.
43. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 809-10.
44. 0 Edward A. Purcell Jr., The Crisis of Democratic Theory: Scientific Naturalism and the Problem of Value (1973).
45. 0 Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind (1930).
47. 0 Fuller's 1934 article on American legal realism in the University of Pennsylvania Law Review is sometimes taken to be a resolute rejection of that philosophy. Lon Fuller, American Legal Realism, 82 U. Pa. L. Rev. 429 (1934). I think this would be stretching the point. In fact, Fuller gives an admiring account of the benefits of legal realism in moving legal scholars away from conceptualism. The quote that begins this article is a good example. Not content merely to praise, Fuller adopts as his own ideas that have a strongly realist tinge. "The intellectual torture which our courts inflict on legal doctrine will be obviated when we have brought ourselves to the point where we are willing to accept as sufficient justification for a decision the "non-technical" considerations which really motivated it." Id. at 435. Fuller does criticize the realists in general and Llewellyn in particular, for a number of mistakes. But the overall tenor of his analysis is that of a friendly and supportive critic. Thus he agrees with the realists' insistence on functional analysis of legal rules, agrees with their critique of conceptualism and their claim that judges are significantly unconstrained by legal doctrine tout seul but argues that general acceptance of these ideas will actually lead to greater certainty and predictability in the legal system.
"If you put an animal in too small an enclosure you may rely on it that he will make a violent effort to escape. There is no way of predicting whether he will succeed in this effort, or where he will go if he breaks out. If you put him in a larger enclosure you may be reasonably sure that he will be content to stay inside the enclosure. And if you study your animal's habits closely you will be able to follow his movements within the enclosure and discover regularities in them. What we need, as I see it, is a larger grazing area for judges. The realists are bringing this about, and they ought to realise that in doing so they are making the judge a more tractable and predictable animal." Id. at 437. (emphasis added)
55. 0 Thirty years later, Roberto Unger was to use an almost identical analysis of the antinomy between formal and substantive justice in order to ground his critique of liberal legalism. "A system of laws or rules can neither dispense with a consideration of values in the process of adjudication, nor be made compatible with such a consideration. Moreover, judgments about how to further general rules in particular situations (substantive justice) can neither do without rules, nor be made compatible with them." Roberto M. Unger, Knowledge and Politics 91 (1976).
56. 0 From Fuller's point of view, even the invocation of practical politicians, adminstrators or engineers as role models implies that some formal limitations are accepted on the rôle of the judge.
57. 0 At one point, for example, Foster engages in a puposive interpretation of a statute in a way strikingly reminiscent of the interpretive practice advocated by Lon Fuller in his debates with Hart. Keen then subjects him to merciless critique. "My brother thinks he knows exactly what was sought when men made murder a crime and that was something he calls 'deterrence.' My brother Tatting had already shown how much is passed over in this interpretation. But I think the trouble goes deeper. I doubt very much whether our statute making murder a crime really has a 'purpose' in any ordinary sense of that term." Fuller, supra note 16, at 18.
58. 0 Fuller, supra note 47, at 1.
60. 0 Fuller, supra note 8, at 806.
61. 0 I use this term, like Fuller, to mean either the social aim that contract fosters, or the principle that it embodies. For the moment, the differences between more or less utilitarian accounts is not central to my analysis here.
62. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 811.
63. 0 See Atiyah, supra note 6, at 676.
64. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 808. Fuller's arguments stress the benefits of such an interpretive method to the security of transactions and the consequent enhancement of the "liberty" of all. Id. This is also, of course, a familiar argument for certain understandings of the social contract as well. Other writers have sought to connect the vision of private autonomy to the conception of contract as promise and thus to find interpretive guidance in the same social conventions that are postulated to give promises their moral force. See generally Charles Fried, Contract as Promise (1982).
65. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 809-10.
66. 0 Id. at 811-12. I am indebted to Professor Atiyah's article for pointing out the flaws in Fuller's attempt to reconcile reliance with autonomy.
67. 0 Whether he was right about the consistency of his ideas with the goal of private autonomy, is quite another question.
68. 0 "The traditional social contract and the classical legal contract are similar in structure and function. With respect to structure, both involve
a two-fold relation: the relation that the parties to the contract establish among themselves and the relation between the contractors and the sovereign, which is the interpreter and enforcer of the contract. With respect to function, the similarities are also quite apparent. Indeed, both classical legal contract and traditional social contract are used to dismantle the entrenched institutional framework that binds and subordinates the individual. After having disengaged the individual from the fetters of custom, both the social contract and the legal contract are used as vehicles to reconstruct the sociopolitical universe from the standpoint of the autonomous will of free individuals. By the means of abstraction and reciprocity, these paradigms forge a path of intersubjective relations that is separate and distinct from the will of any of the individual contractors, but which is, nevertheless, determined exclusively by the confluence of their respective individual wills." Michael Rosenfeld, Contract and Justice: The Relation Between Classical Contract Law and Social Contract Theory, 70 Iowa L.Rev. 769 (1985).
69. 0 See Henry Sumner Maine, Ancient Law 165 (1864).
70. 0 "Were you to preach, in most parts of the world, that political connexions are founded altogether on voluntary consent or a mutual promise, the magistrate would soon imprison you, as seditious, for
loosening the ties of obedience, if your friends did not before shut you up as delirious for advancing such absurdities....Almost all the governments which exist at present, or of which there remains any record in story, have been founded originally either on usurpation or conquest, or both, without any pretence of a fair consent or voluntary subjection of the people." David Hume, Theory of Politics 198-9 (Frederick Watkins ed. 1953).
71. 0 I say closely cognate, because the framers of the constitution are understood, like Lycurgus, to have laid down the fundamental laws of the society. Admittedly, there are problems in understanding the Constitutional Convention as locus for the social contract. Who precisely are the parties to such a contract? How are future generations to be bound? How real was the consent and so on. My point is that the same problems beset any theory of the social contract, and that both constitutional scholarship and popular speechways give evidence of the notion that the framing of the constitution is understood as the decision of the people to bind themselves.
72. 0 Robert Bork, The Constitution, Original Intent and Economic Rights, 23 San Diego L. Rev. 823 (1986).
73. 0 Henry Monaghan, Stare Decisis and Constitutional Adjudication, 88 Colum. L. Rev. 723 (1988).
74. 0 Morton J. Horwitz, Transformation of American Law, 1780-1860, 180-88 (1977).
75. 0 Robert Bork, The Tempting of America (1991). For the full details of this, and other, transformations in Mr. Bork's legal philosophy see James Boyle, A Process of Denial: Bork and Post-Modern Conservatism, 3 Yale J. L. & Human. 263, 281-90 (1991).
76. 0 Bork, supra note 74, at 139-60.
78. 0 Fuller, supra note 10, at 803. (emphasis in original)
80. 0 I am not suggesting that it is necessary to give up the prohibition of retroactive legislation in such a society. My argument is that, if we followed Fuller's hints from Consideration and Form, we would have to lay out clearly the reasons for prohibiting retroactive legislation and to decide whether the premises on which the prohibition relied were convincing in this particular set of circumstances, or whether they achieved their force through definitional sleight of hand. For example, one argument against retroactivity focuses on the unfairness of applying to a natural or legal person a rule which was not in existence at the time when the relevant conduct took place. At the same time, we are willing to apply rules to those who have no knowledge of them, on the grounds that ignorance of the law is no excuse. Does the distinction here depend on an assumption that knowledge of the rules is 'equally available' to citizens, provided publication does take place? Is this presumption a factual one, or does it depend on the acceptance of some other principle of formal equality as a subsidiary premise of the juriprudential scheme? If so, is Fuller arguing that the very ideal of the rule of law demands that we adopt classical liberal asuumptions about formal equality, so that no society which challenged these assumptions -- whether through affirmative action or an expansive doctrine of unconscionability in private contracts -- would count as a law-governed society?
81. 0 Consider also the following example, "[s]o far as the channeling function of a formality is concerned it has no place where men's activities are already divided into definite clear-cut business categories. Where life has already organised itself effectively, there is no need for the law to intervene. It is for this reason that important transactions on the stock and produce markets can safey be carried out in the most 'informal' manner." Fuller, supra note 10, at 806. Note the insistence on first enunciating the
goal served by a particular form and then examining whether that goal is achieved in a particular context.
82. 0 The story of King Rex which Fuller uses to make his points is instructive, for it becomes clear that while it is jurisprudentially irrelevant whether or not the society has any shred of democratic governance, the form of the norms issued to the populace is all important. This is an ethically thin conception of the rule of law.
83. 0 Fuller, supra note 2, at 96 (emphasis added).
85. 0 Fuller, supra note 47, at 7.
86. 0 Fuller lists as the first of the eight ways to fail to make law "a failure to achieve rules at all, so that every issue must be decided on an ad hoc basis." Fuller, supra note 2, at 39.
87. 0 Fuller, supra note 1, at 435.
89. 0 26 Wis. 2d 683, 133 N.W.2d 267 (1965).
90. 0 Hume, supra note 69, at 203.
91. 0 A. John Simmons, Moral Principles and Political Obligations 68 (1979).
92. 0 Slawson, Standard Form Contracts and Democratic Control of Lawmaking Power, 84 Harv. L. Rev. 529 (1971).
93. 0 For example, Charles Fried finds the roots of the binding quality of promises in a morality of autonomy, a social convention that gives intersubjective meaning to the act of promising, and an existential account of the possibilities of self-realization that such a system offers. Charles Fried, Contract as Promise (1982). It is also interesting to note that Fried's book includes a generous tribute to Fuller. The fact that Fuller's ideas influenced Roberto Unger's account of interpretation, Duncan Kennedy's analysis of rules and standards and Charles Fried's analysis of contract as promise, gives some sense of the range of their appeal. My sense is that it would be possible to show the evolution of the tensions I describe here through the works of contemporary theorists who have been influenced by Fuller's work. That task, however, must wait for another occasion.
94. 0 Fuller, supra note 2, at 39.
95. 0 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (London 1740); James Boyle, Modernist Social Theory: Roberto Unger's Passion, 98 Harv L. Rev. 1066, 1071-77 (1985) (book review).
96. 0 Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue 54-55, 122-245 (1981).
97. 0 Id. at 55-56. (emphasis added)
98. 0 It also seems to the be the line that contemporary contractarian philosophers find most convincing. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (1971); Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974); Joseph Raz, The Morality of Freedom (1988).
99. 0 For an interesting contemporary argument coming to the same conclusion see Richard H. Fallon, Jr., Reflections on Dworkin and the Two Faces of Law 67 Notre Dame L. Rev. 553 (1992).
100. 0 Apart from the general problems of idealist legal history, the degree of inspiration offered by Fuller, rather than by the realist movement generally is in considerable doubt. This issue is complicated by Fuller's own contradictory feelings about realism and by the accidents of law school tradition and pedagogic influence. If citation and syllabi are anything to go by, Fuller seems to have had more of a direct influence on the first three thinkers in my list.