I The Internet Trinity | II Foucault & Digital Libertarianism | III Safe Harbours and Unintended Consequences | IV Privatised Panopticons and Legalised Enclosures | V A Communications Sampler | Conclusion |
When Netizens think of law, they tend to conjure up a positivist, even
Austinian image;(15) law is a command backed
by threats, issued by a sovereign who acknowledges no superior, directed
to a geographically defined population which renders that sovereign habitual
obedience.(16) Thus they think of the state's
laws as blunt instruments incapable of imposing their will on the global
subjects of the Net and their evanescent and geographically unsituated
transactions. Indeed, if there was ever a model of law designed to fail
at regulating the Net, it is the Austinian model. Fortunately or unfortunately
for the Net, however, the Austinian model is both crude and inaccurate,
and that is where the work of the late Michel Foucault comes in.
Michel Foucault was one of the most interesting of post war French philosophers
and social theorists. His work was wide-ranging, sometimes obscure,(17)
indeed deliberately so, and his historical generalisations would have been
be insufferable if they were not so often provocatively useful.(18)
Above all, Foucault had the knack of posing problems in a new way -- re-orienting
the inquiry in a way that was manifestly helpful for those who followed.
This facility has been testified to by thinkers whose politics and methodology
are very far from Foucault's own.(19)
From the point of view of this article, one of Foucault's most interesting
contributions was to challenge a particular notion of power, power-as-sovereignty,
and to juxtapose against it a vision of "surveillance" and of
"discipline."(20) At the heart
of this project was a belief that both our analyses of the operation of
political power and our strategies for its restraint or limitation were
inaccurate and misguided. In a series of essays and books, Foucault argued
that, rather than the public and formal triangle of sovereign, citizen
and right, we should focus on a series of subtler, private, informal and
material forms of coercion organised around the concepts of "discipline"
and "surveillance." The paradigm for the idea of surveillance
was the Panopticon, Bentham's plan for a prison constructed in the shape
of a wheel around the hub of an observing warden, who at any moment might
have the prisoner under observation through a nineteenth century version
of the closed circuit TV.(21) Unsure of
when authority might in fact be watching, the prisoner would strive always
to conform his behaviour to its presumed desires; Bentham had struck upon
a behavioralist equivalent of the superego, formed from uncertainty about
when one was being observed by the powers that be. The echo of contemporary
laments about the 'privacy-free state' is striking. To this Foucault added
the notion of discipline -- crudely put, the multitudinous "private"
methods of regulation of individual behaviour ranging from workplace time-and-motion
efficiency directives to psychiatric evaluation.(22)
Foucault pointed out the apparent conflict between a formal language
of politics organised around relations between sovereign and citizen, expressed
through rules backed by sanctions, and an actual experience of power being
exercised through multitudinous non-state sources, often dependent on material
or technological means of enforcement. Writing in a manner that managed
to be simultaneously coy and sinister, Foucault suggested that there was
something strange going on in the coexistence of these two systems.
Impossible to describe in the terminology of the theory of sovereignty
from which it differs so radically, this disciplinary power ought by rights
to have led to the disappearance of the grand juridical edifice created
by that theory. But in reality, the theory of sovereignty has continued
to exist not only as an ideology of right, but also to provide the organising
principle of the legal codes.... Why has the theory of sovereignty persisted
in this fashion..? For two reasons, I believe. On the one hand, it has
been.. a permanent instrument of criticism of the monarchy and all the
obstacles that can thwart the development of a disciplinary society. But
at the same time, the theory of sovereignty, and the organisation of a
legal code centered upon it, have allowed a system of right to be superimposed
upon the mechanism[] of discipline in such a way as to conceal its actual
procedures ....(23)
Foucault was not writing about the Internet. He was not even writing
about the twentieth century. But his words provide a good starting place
from which to examine the catechism of Net inviolability. They are a good
starting point precisely because, when viewed within the discourse of sovereignty,
of the promulgation and enforcement of Austinian "commands backed
by threats" aimed at a defined territory and population, the Net does
indeed look almost invulnerable. Things look rather different when viewed
from the perspective of "a type of power which is constantly exercised
by means of surveillance rather than in a discontinuous manner by means
of a system of levies or obligations distributed over time [and which]...
presupposes a tightly knit grid of material coercions rather than the physical
existence of a sovereign." What's more, there is a sense in which
the "system of right [is] superimposed upon the mechanism[] of discipline
in such a way as to conceal its actual procedures"; the jurisprudence
of digital libertarianism is not simply inaccurate, it may actually obscure
our understanding of what is going on. Thus even the digerati may find
the analysis that follows of interest; if only to see how far the Net can
be made to treat censorship as a feature not a bug, how far local ordinances
may reach in cyberspace, and how information's 'desire for freedom' may
be curbed.
The examples I will give are drawn from different areas of regulation
of communications technology. Some of them deal explicitly with the Internet:
the Communications Decency Act, the proposed NII Copyright Protection Act,
the regulation of cryptography. Others are directed towards technologies
outside of the Net, at least for the present: the V-chip, the Clipper chip,
digital telephony and digital audio recorders. All of them share one thing
-- the state has worked actively to embed or hardwire the legal regime
in the technology itself.(24) In most of
them, the exercise of power is much more a matter of the quotidian shaping
and surveillance of activity than of imposing sanctions after the fact.
Yet these examples also present revealing differences -- illustrating a
range of goals, tactics and results. Sometimes technology has been mandated
by legislation, sometimes facilitated through state-sanctioned standard-setting
bodies. Sometimes the legislation defines technological safe-harbours to
sanctions that would otherwise apply and sometimes the state uses the power
of the purse to create a de facto standard by refusing to purchase
any equipment that does not conform to the desired technical/legal standards.
I will begin with the Communications Decency Act, turn to the use of strict
liability and digital fences in internet copyright policy and conclude
with a sampler of hardwired regulation, drawn from a number of areas of
communications technology.
I The Internet Trinity | II Foucault & Digital Libertarianism | III Safe Harbours and Unintended Consequences | IV Privatised Panopticons and Legalised Enclosures | V A Communications Sampler | Conclusion |
ENDNOTES FOR SECTION II
15. John Austin, The Province Of Jurisprudence Determined (H.L.A. Hart ed. 1954) See also James Boyle, Thomas Hobbes and the Invented Tradition of Positivism: Reflections on Language, Power, and Essentialism, 135 U. Pa. L. Rev. 383 (Jan. 1987).
16. One of the reasons for this may be the overwhelmingly libertarian cast to Internet politics in the United States. Libertarians tend to concentrate on state power rather than private power, they tend to focus on the obvious restraints on freedom imposed by criminal law's impact against the citizen, rather than the subtler restraints imposed by the rules constituting and structuring market and other relationships. Both ideas 'fit' the Austinian image. By making a criminal statute the paradigm of the exercise of state power, and the citizen's right against the government the paradigm of its limitation, the libertarian codes his normative ideas about political problems and solutions into the very image of law itself.
17. "You will recall my work here, such as it has been ... None of it does more than mark time. Repetitive and disconnected, it advances nowhere. Since indeed it never ceases to say the same thing, it perhaps says nothing. It is tangled up into an indecipherable, disorganised muddle. In a nutshell, it is inconclusive. Still, I could claim that after all these were only trails to be followed, it mattered little where they led; indeed, it was important that they did not have a predetermined starting point and destination. They were merely lines laid down for you to pursue or to divert elsewhere, or re-design as the case might be. They are, in the final analysis, just fragments, and it is up to you or me to see what we can make of them. For my part, it has struck me that I might have seemed a bit like a whale that leaps to the surface of the water disturbing it momentarily with a tiny jet of spray and lets it be believed, or pretends to believe, or wants to believe, or himself does in fact believe, that down in the depths where no one sees him any more, where he is no longer witnessed nor controlled by anyone, he follows a more profound, coherent and reasoned trajectory. Well, anyway, that was more or less how I at least conceived the situation; it could be that you perceived it differently." Michel Foucault, Two Lectures, in Michael Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977, 78-79 (Colin Gordon ed. & Colin Gordon et al. trans., 1980).
18. What Is an Author?, in Textual Strategies: Perspectives In Post-Structuralist Criticism 141 (Josue V. Harari ed., 1979), Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (Alan Sheridan ed. & trans., 1979)
19. See, e.g., Richard Posner, Sex and Reason at 23, 182 (Harv. Univ. Press 1992) (describing Foucault's writings on sexuality as "remarkable" and "eloquent").
20. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison (Alan Sheridan ed. & trans., 1979)
21. Janet Semple, Bentham's Prison: A Study of the Panopticon Penitentiary (1993); The two writers to have used Foucault's ideas most notably in the legal privacy and cyberspace context are J.M. Balkin, What is a Postmodern Constitutionalism? 90 Mich. L. Rev. 1966, 1987 (1992) and Larry Lessig, Reading the Constitution in Cyberspace, 45 Emory L. J. 869, 895 (Summer 1996) (citing Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison at 139-40 (Alan Sheridan ed. & trans., 1979)).
22. In many ways, Foucault himself was most interested in a portion of this analysis that I shall pursue here only episodically. In a series of works on the treatment of insanity and on penology he argued that the emergence of the academic and intellectual "disciplines" as we know them now is reciprocally linked in important ways to this minute and quotidian regulation of behaviour. At the same time, retrofitting some of his earlier work on the human sciences into this new theoretical mold, he suggested that our conception of "an individual" was not some naturally occurring fact of nature from which analyses could begin, but instead, in part, a result of the concatenation of discipline and surveillance. Elsewhere I have explored the connections between power and knowledge (James Boyle, The Politics of Reason: Critical Legal Theory and Local Social Thought, 133 U. Pa. L. Rev. 685 (April 1995)), and the effects of the construction of subjectivity (James Boyle, Is Subjectivity Possible? The Postmodern Subject in Legal Theory, 62 U. Co. L. Rev. 489 (1991)). While there are interesting things to be said about the construction of subjectivity in cyberspace, my goal here is more mundane.
23. Michel Foucault, Two Lectures, in Michael Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-1977, 78, 105 (Colin Gordon ed. & Colin Gordon et al. trans., 1980).
24. The best, and often the only, chronicler of the role of hard and softwired regimes is Lawrence Lessig. "I don't take issue with the values inherent in any one particular system of code. My criticism is directed against those who think about cyber regulation solely in terms of "law." Laws affect the pace of technologicalchange, but the strictures of software can do even more to curtail freedom. In the long run, the shackles built by programmers may well constrain us most." Cyber Rights Now: Tyranny in the Infrastructure Wired 5:07 (June 1997) http://wwww.wired.com/wired/5.07/crn/index.html See also Lawrence Lessig, The Zones of Cyberspace 48 Stan. L. Rev. 1403, 1408. " In the well implemented system, there is no civil disobedience. Law as code is a start to the perfect technology of justice."